Facebook Pixel
Searching...
English
EnglishEnglish
EspañolSpanish
简体中文Chinese
FrançaisFrench
DeutschGerman
日本語Japanese
PortuguêsPortuguese
ItalianoItalian
한국어Korean
РусскийRussian
NederlandsDutch
العربيةArabic
PolskiPolish
हिन्दीHindi
Tiếng ViệtVietnamese
SvenskaSwedish
ΕλληνικάGreek
TürkçeTurkish
ไทยThai
ČeštinaCzech
RomânăRomanian
MagyarHungarian
УкраїнськаUkrainian
Bahasa IndonesiaIndonesian
DanskDanish
SuomiFinnish
БългарскиBulgarian
עבריתHebrew
NorskNorwegian
HrvatskiCroatian
CatalàCatalan
SlovenčinaSlovak
LietuviųLithuanian
SlovenščinaSlovenian
СрпскиSerbian
EestiEstonian
LatviešuLatvian
فارسیPersian
മലയാളംMalayalam
தமிழ்Tamil
اردوUrdu
Utilitarianism

Utilitarianism

by John Stuart Mill 1861 71 pages
3.68
24k+ ratings
Listen
Listen to Summary

Key Takeaways

1. Utilitarianism: The Greatest Happiness Principle

The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to produce the reverse of happiness.

Core of Utilitarianism. Utilitarianism, at its heart, is a moral philosophy centered around the idea that the best actions are those that maximize happiness and minimize suffering. This principle, often called the "Greatest Happiness Principle," serves as a guide for evaluating the morality of actions, policies, and even personal choices. It posits that the ultimate goal of ethical behavior is to create the greatest amount of happiness for the greatest number of people.

Bentham and Mill. While the roots of utilitarianism can be traced back to ancient philosophers like Epicurus, it was Jeremy Bentham and John Stuart Mill who formalized and popularized the theory. Bentham focused on quantifying happiness, while Mill refined the concept by introducing the idea of qualitative differences in pleasures. Their work laid the foundation for modern utilitarian thought.

Practical Applications. Utilitarianism has broad implications for various fields, including law, economics, and public policy. For example, a utilitarian approach to criminal justice might emphasize rehabilitation and crime prevention over retribution, aiming to reduce overall suffering in society. Similarly, in economics, utilitarianism can justify policies that promote wealth redistribution if they lead to a net increase in overall happiness.

2. Pleasure and the Absence of Pain as the Ultimate Good

By happiness is intended pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the privation of pleasure.

Defining Happiness. Utilitarianism equates happiness with pleasure and the absence of pain. This doesn't necessarily mean hedonistic indulgence, but rather a state of overall well-being and satisfaction. It acknowledges that life inevitably involves some degree of pain and suffering, but the goal is to minimize these negative experiences and maximize positive ones.

Beyond Physical Sensations. While physical pleasures are certainly included in the utilitarian calculus, the concept of pleasure extends far beyond mere sensory gratification. Intellectual, emotional, and social pleasures are also considered important components of happiness. For example, the satisfaction derived from learning, creating, or helping others can be just as valuable, if not more so, than physical pleasures.

Measuring Happiness. One of the challenges of utilitarianism is how to measure and compare different types of pleasure and pain. Bentham proposed a "felicific calculus" that takes into account factors such as intensity, duration, certainty, and propinquity. While this approach has been criticized for being overly simplistic, it highlights the importance of considering the various dimensions of happiness when making ethical decisions.

3. Higher vs. Lower Pleasures: Quality Matters

It is quite compatible with the principle of utility to recognise the fact, that some kinds of pleasure are more desirable and more valuable than others.

Mill's Refinement. John Stuart Mill argued that not all pleasures are created equal. He distinguished between "higher" and "lower" pleasures, with higher pleasures being those that engage our intellectual and moral faculties, while lower pleasures are those that are primarily sensory or physical. This distinction was a response to critics who accused utilitarianism of being a "doctrine worthy only of swine."

Competent Judges. According to Mill, the best way to determine the relative value of different pleasures is to consult the judgment of "competent judges" – those who have experienced both types of pleasure and are capable of appreciating their respective qualities. Mill believed that such judges would consistently prefer higher pleasures over lower ones, even if the latter were more intense or readily available.

Examples of Higher and Lower Pleasures:

  • Higher: Intellectual pursuits, artistic appreciation, moral acts, creative endeavors
  • Lower: Eating, drinking, sex, physical comfort

Mill's emphasis on the quality of pleasures adds a layer of complexity to utilitarianism, but it also makes the theory more palatable to those who value intellectual and moral development.

4. Happiness for All, Not Just the Individual

The standard is not the agent's own greatest happiness, but the greatest amount of happiness altogether.

Impartiality. Utilitarianism is not about maximizing one's own happiness at the expense of others. Rather, it requires us to consider the happiness of all sentient beings affected by our actions. This means adopting an impartial perspective and weighing the interests of everyone equally.

The Role of Benevolence. Utilitarianism encourages benevolence and altruism, as these qualities tend to promote overall happiness. However, it's not simply about being nice or feeling good; it's about making choices that have the greatest positive impact on the well-being of others. This may sometimes require difficult decisions or even personal sacrifices.

Global Perspective. The scope of utilitarianism extends beyond national borders and cultural boundaries. It calls for us to consider the well-being of all people, regardless of their location or background. This has implications for issues such as global poverty, environmental protection, and international relations.

5. Addressing the "Unhappiness" Objection

When, however, it is thus positively asserted to be impossible that human life should be happy, the assertion, if not something like a verbal quibble, is at least an exaggeration.

Realistic Expectations. Critics often argue that happiness is unattainable, and therefore cannot be a realistic goal for morality. Mill counters that utilitarianism doesn't require a constant state of ecstatic bliss. Rather, it aims for a life that is largely free from pain and rich in various forms of pleasure.

Tranquility and Excitement. Mill identifies two key components of a satisfying life: tranquility and excitement. Tranquility provides a sense of peace and contentment, while excitement adds novelty and stimulation. A balanced combination of these two elements is essential for long-term happiness.

External Factors. Mill acknowledges that external factors such as poverty, disease, and social injustice can significantly hinder happiness. However, he argues that these obstacles are largely removable through social progress and individual effort. Utilitarianism, therefore, provides a framework for addressing these issues and creating a more equitable and fulfilling society.

6. The Role of Self-Sacrifice in Utilitarianism

All honour to those who can abnegate for themselves the personal enjoyment of life, when by such renunciation they contribute worthily to increase the amount of happiness in the world.

Not an End in Itself. Utilitarianism doesn't glorify self-sacrifice as an end in itself. Rather, it values self-sacrifice only insofar as it contributes to the overall happiness of others. A sacrifice that doesn't increase the sum total of happiness is considered pointless or even harmful.

The Greater Good. Utilitarianism may require individuals to make sacrifices for the greater good. For example, a soldier might risk their life to protect their comrades, or a philanthropist might donate a large portion of their wealth to alleviate poverty. In these cases, the sacrifice is justified because it leads to a net increase in overall happiness.

Limits to Sacrifice. While utilitarianism may call for self-sacrifice, it also recognizes the importance of individual well-being. It doesn't demand that people constantly deny themselves pleasure or neglect their own needs. A healthy balance between self-interest and altruism is essential for a sustainable and fulfilling life.

7. The Sanctions of Utility: Internal and External

The internal sanction of duty, whatever our standard of duty may be, is one and the same—a feeling in our own mind; a pain, more or less intense, attendant on violation of duty, which in properly cultivated moral natures rises, in the more serious cases, into shrinking from it as an impossibility.

Motivations for Obedience. Every moral standard needs a "sanction," or a reason why people should follow it. Utilitarianism, like other moral systems, has both external and internal sanctions that encourage adherence to its principles. These sanctions provide the motivation for individuals to act in accordance with the Greatest Happiness Principle.

External Sanctions. External sanctions include the fear of punishment and the hope of reward, both from other people and from a divine being. Social pressure, legal penalties, and religious beliefs can all serve as external incentives for promoting happiness and avoiding actions that cause harm.

Internal Sanctions. The internal sanction of utilitarianism is conscience – the feeling of guilt or remorse that arises when we violate our own moral standards. This internal sanction is cultivated through education and experience, and it becomes a powerful force for guiding our behavior. Mill believed that a well-developed conscience is essential for a truly moral life.

8. Proof of Utility: Desirability and Human Nature

The sole evidence it is possible to produce that anything is desirable, is that people do actually desire it.

The Question of Proof. Utilitarianism, as a theory about ultimate ends, cannot be proven in the same way that scientific claims can be proven. However, Mill argues that it can be supported by appealing to human experience and observation. The fact that people desire happiness is, according to Mill, the best possible evidence that happiness is desirable.

Virtue as Part of Happiness. Critics often point out that people desire things other than happiness, such as virtue, knowledge, or power. Mill responds that these things are not desired as separate ends, but rather as components of happiness. Virtue, for example, may initially be valued as a means to happiness, but it can eventually become a source of intrinsic pleasure and a part of one's overall well-being.

The Role of Will. Mill acknowledges that will is distinct from desire, and that people can act against their desires out of habit or principle. However, he argues that will is ultimately rooted in desire, and that the best way to cultivate virtuous behavior is to associate it with pleasure and avoid associating it with pain.

9. Justice and Utility: Reconciling the Two

In all ages of speculation, one of the strongest obstacles to the reception of the doctrine that Utility or Happiness is the criterion of right and wrong, has been drawn from the idea of Justice.

The Apparent Conflict. Justice, with its strong emotional and intuitive appeal, often seems to conflict with the utilitarian emphasis on maximizing overall happiness. Critics argue that utilitarianism can justify unjust actions if they lead to a greater good for society as a whole. This raises concerns about the protection of individual rights and the fairness of social institutions.

Justice as a Derivative of Utility. Mill argues that justice is not a separate and independent principle, but rather a subset of utility. He contends that the rules of justice are those that are most essential to human well-being and that have the strongest claim on our obedience. These rules are designed to protect fundamental rights and ensure a stable and predictable social order.

The Importance of Security. Mill emphasizes the importance of security as a vital component of human happiness. He argues that the rules of justice are primarily concerned with protecting individuals from harm and ensuring their ability to pursue their own goals without fear of interference. This focus on security helps to explain the strong emotional attachment we have to the concept of justice.

10. Justice as a Subset of Utility: Security and Rights

Justice is a name for certain classes of moral rules, which concern the essentials of human well-being more nearly, and are therefore of more absolute obligation, than any other rules for the guidance of life; and the notion which we have found to be of the essence of the idea of justice, that of a right residing in an individual, implies and testifies to this more binding obligation.

Rights and Obligations. Mill connects the concept of justice to the idea of rights. He argues that when we say someone has a right to something, we mean that society has an obligation to protect them in the possession of it. These rights are not absolute or inherent, but rather are derived from considerations of utility.

The Role of Society. According to Mill, society has a responsibility to ensure that individuals are able to exercise their rights and that their basic needs are met. This may require the establishment of laws, institutions, and social programs that promote fairness and equality.

The Ultimate Appeal to Utility. In cases where different principles of justice conflict, Mill argues that the ultimate appeal must be to utility. The goal is to find the solution that maximizes overall happiness while minimizing harm to individuals. This requires careful consideration of the consequences of different actions and a commitment to impartiality and fairness.

Last updated:

Review Summary

3.68 out of 5
Average of 24k+ ratings from Goodreads and Amazon.

Utilitarianism by John Stuart Mill is a short but influential philosophical work on ethics. Many readers found it challenging but rewarding, praising Mill's clear arguments for the greatest happiness principle. The book defends utilitarianism against common criticisms and explores its relationship to justice. While some found parts difficult or disagreed with Mill's conclusions, many appreciated its impact on moral philosophy and social sciences. Several reviewers noted its continued relevance to modern ethical debates.

Your rating:

About the Author

John Stuart Mill was a prominent 19th-century English philosopher, economist, and politician. Born in 1806, he was given an intensive education by his father James Mill and philosopher Jeremy Bentham. Mill became a leading proponent of utilitarianism, though his version differed from Bentham's. He was a prolific writer on topics including logic, economics, politics, and ethics. His works, including "On Liberty" and "Utilitarianism," have been highly influential in liberal political thought. Mill served as a Member of Parliament and was known for his advocacy of women's rights and individual liberty. His contributions to philosophy and social theory continue to be studied and debated today.

0:00
-0:00
1x
Dan
Andrew
Michelle
Lauren
Select Speed
1.0×
+
200 words per minute
Home
Library
Get App
Create a free account to unlock:
Requests: Request new book summaries
Bookmarks: Save your favorite books
History: Revisit books later
Recommendations: Get personalized suggestions
Ratings: Rate books & see your ratings
Try Full Access for 7 Days
Listen, bookmark, and more
Compare Features Free Pro
📖 Read Summaries
All summaries are free to read in 40 languages
🎧 Listen to Summaries
Listen to unlimited summaries in 40 languages
❤️ Unlimited Bookmarks
Free users are limited to 10
📜 Unlimited History
Free users are limited to 10
Risk-Free Timeline
Today: Get Instant Access
Listen to full summaries of 73,530 books. That's 12,000+ hours of audio!
Day 4: Trial Reminder
We'll send you a notification that your trial is ending soon.
Day 7: Your subscription begins
You'll be charged on Apr 11,
cancel anytime before.
Consume 2.8x More Books
2.8x more books Listening Reading
Our users love us
100,000+ readers
"...I can 10x the number of books I can read..."
"...exceptionally accurate, engaging, and beautifully presented..."
"...better than any amazon review when I'm making a book-buying decision..."
Save 62%
Yearly
$119.88 $44.99/year
$3.75/mo
Monthly
$9.99/mo
Try Free & Unlock
7 days free, then $44.99/year. Cancel anytime.
Scanner
Find a barcode to scan

Settings
General
Widget
Appearance
Loading...
Black Friday Sale 🎉
$20 off Lifetime Access
$79.99 $59.99
Upgrade Now →