Facebook Pixel
Searching...
English
EnglishEnglish
EspañolSpanish
简体中文Chinese
FrançaisFrench
DeutschGerman
日本語Japanese
PortuguêsPortuguese
ItalianoItalian
한국어Korean
РусскийRussian
NederlandsDutch
العربيةArabic
PolskiPolish
हिन्दीHindi
Tiếng ViệtVietnamese
SvenskaSwedish
ΕλληνικάGreek
TürkçeTurkish
ไทยThai
ČeštinaCzech
RomânăRomanian
MagyarHungarian
УкраїнськаUkrainian
Bahasa IndonesiaIndonesian
DanskDanish
SuomiFinnish
БългарскиBulgarian
עבריתHebrew
NorskNorwegian
HrvatskiCroatian
CatalàCatalan
SlovenčinaSlovak
LietuviųLithuanian
SlovenščinaSlovenian
СрпскиSerbian
EestiEstonian
LatviešuLatvian
فارسیPersian
മലയാളംMalayalam
தமிழ்Tamil
اردوUrdu
Philosophical Investigations

Philosophical Investigations

by Ludwig Wittgenstein 1953 246 pages
4.26
15k+ ratings
Listen
Listen to Summary

Key Takeaways

1. Language Meaning is Use, Not Just Naming

For a large class of cases—though not for all—in which we employ the word "meaning" it can be defined thus: the meaning of a word is its use in the language.

Against the Augustinian picture. Wittgenstein challenges the traditional view, exemplified by Augustine, that language primarily functions by naming objects. This "naming" view oversimplifies the complexity of language, ignoring the diverse roles words play and the contexts in which they are used. Instead, he proposes that the meaning of a word is found in its practical application within a language.

Use over reference. The focus shifts from a word's reference (what it points to) to its use (how it functions). Consider the word "slab" in a simple language-game between a builder and his assistant. The meaning of "slab" isn't just the object itself, but the action it prompts: bringing the slab. This emphasis on use highlights the active, dynamic nature of language.

Beyond simple definitions. This perspective dissolves the haze surrounding the concept of meaning. By examining language in primitive, clear-cut applications, we can better understand how words function. This approach emphasizes the importance of context and the active role of language users in creating meaning.

2. Language-Games: Words in Action

I will call these games "language-games" and will sometimes speak of a primitive language as a language-game.

Language as activity. Wittgenstein introduces the concept of "language-games" to emphasize that language is not merely a system of representation but an integral part of human activity. Speaking a language is like playing a game, with its own rules, strategies, and goals.

Multiplicity of games. There are countless language-games, each with its own unique set of rules and purposes. Examples include:

  • Giving orders and obeying them
  • Describing an object's appearance
  • Reporting an event
  • Making up a story
  • Asking, thanking, cursing, greeting, praying

Form of life. Understanding a language-game requires understanding the "form of life" in which it is embedded. Language is not an isolated phenomenon but is interwoven with our actions, customs, and social practices. To learn a language is to learn a way of life.

3. Family Resemblances: Concepts Without Rigid Boundaries

I can think of no better expression to characterize these similarities than "family resemblances"; for the various resemblances between members of a family: build, features, colour of eyes, gait, temperament, etc. etc. overlap and criss-cross in the same way.

Rejecting essentialism. Wittgenstein argues against the idea that concepts have fixed, essential properties common to all instances. Instead, he proposes that concepts are like families, with members sharing overlapping and crisscrossing similarities, but no single feature present in all.

The concept of "game." Consider the concept of "game." Board games, card games, ball games, and Olympic games all fall under this category, yet they share no single defining characteristic. Some are amusing, some involve competition, some require skill, and some rely on luck.

Blurred edges. Concepts are not defined by rigid boundaries but by a network of similarities. This "blurred edges" approach acknowledges the flexibility and adaptability of language, allowing for new instances and variations to be included without disrupting the overall concept.

4. The Illusion of Logic's Sublime Purity

The tendency to assume a pure intermediary between the propositional signs and the facts.

Critique of logical idealism. Wittgenstein challenges the notion that logic provides a perfect, crystalline structure underlying language and thought. He argues that this "sublime" view of logic leads to dissatisfaction with ordinary language and a misguided search for an ideal language.

Language on holiday. Philosophical problems arise when language is "on holiday," that is, when it is divorced from its everyday use. By focusing on idealized systems, philosophers lose sight of the actual functioning of language in real-world contexts.

Back to the rough ground. The solution is not to construct an ideal language but to return to the "rough ground" of ordinary language and examine how words are actually used. This involves dissolving philosophical problems by clarifying the use of language, not by imposing artificial structures upon it.

5. Philosophy as Therapy: Dissolving Misunderstandings

The results of philosophy are the uncovering of one or another piece of plain nonsense and of bumps that the understanding has got by running its head up against the limits of language.

Philosophical problems as linguistic confusions. Wittgenstein views philosophical problems as arising from misunderstandings of language. These misunderstandings are not due to a lack of information but to a distorted way of looking at language and its use.

The task of the philosopher. The philosopher's role is not to provide explanations or solutions but to clarify the use of language and dissolve the confusions that give rise to philosophical problems. This involves assembling reminders of how language is actually used and rearranging our understanding to gain a clear view.

Complete clarity. The goal is not to refine or perfect language but to achieve complete clarity, such that philosophical problems disappear altogether. This therapeutic approach aims to liberate us from the bewitchment of our intelligence by language.

6. The Interplay of Rules, Training, and Agreement

To obey a rule, to make a report, to give an order, to play a game of chess, are customs (uses, institutions).

Rules are not self-interpreting. Rules do not contain their own interpretation. Any rule can be interpreted in multiple ways, and interpretations alone cannot determine meaning. The meaning of a rule is established by how it is applied in practice.

Training and practice. Obeying a rule is a practice, a custom, an institution. We are trained to follow rules in particular ways, and our understanding of a rule is demonstrated by our ability to apply it correctly in various situations.

Agreement in judgment. Language requires agreement not only in definitions but also in judgments. This agreement is not a matter of opinion but a shared form of life, a common way of acting and reacting to the world.

7. The Private Language Argument: Sensations and Shared Meaning

How do words refer to sensations?—There doesn't seem to be any problem here; don't we talk about sensations every day, and give them names? But how is the connexion between the name and the thing named set up?

The impossibility of a private language. Wittgenstein argues against the possibility of a language that only one person can understand. Such a language, based on private sensations, would lack the necessary criteria for correctness and meaning.

Public criteria for sensations. Our words for sensations, like "pain," are not defined by private experiences but by public criteria, such as behavior, expressions, and circumstances. These criteria allow us to communicate about sensations and to understand each other.

Language as a social phenomenon. Language is inherently social. Meaning arises from shared practices and conventions, not from private mental states. A private language, lacking these shared foundations, would be meaningless.

8. The Will: Not a Cause, But Woven into Action

Willing, if it is not to be a sort of wishing, must be the action itself.

Against the separation of will and action. Wittgenstein challenges the traditional view of the will as a separate mental faculty that causes our actions. He argues that willing is not a distinct process but is interwoven with the action itself.

Voluntary movement. Voluntary movement is characterized by the absence of surprise. When I raise my arm, I do not observe it as an external event but experience it as my own action. This experience is not a matter of feeling a special force but of acting without resistance.

Grammar of "I will." The grammar of "I will" is different from that of "I wish." "I will" is an expression of intention, a commitment to a future action, while "I wish" expresses a desire or longing. The two concepts play different roles in our language and lives.

9. Seeing Aspects: A Shift in Understanding

The aspects of things that are most important for us are hidden because of their simplicity and familiarity.

Aspect-seeing as a change in understanding. Wittgenstein introduces the concept of "seeing aspects" to describe how our understanding of an object or situation can suddenly shift, revealing new meanings and possibilities. This is not merely a change in visual impression but a change in how we interpret and engage with the world.

The duck-rabbit example. The duck-rabbit illusion illustrates this concept. The drawing remains the same, but our perception can alternate between seeing a duck and seeing a rabbit. This change is not a matter of adding new information but of reorganizing what we already see.

Beyond visual experience. Seeing aspects is not limited to visual perception. It can also apply to understanding music, poetry, or even social situations. It involves grasping new connections and possibilities, enriching our understanding of the world.

Last updated:

Review Summary

4.26 out of 5
Average of 15k+ ratings from Goodreads and Amazon.

Philosophical Investigations is a complex and influential work in 20th century philosophy. Readers find it challenging but rewarding, praising Wittgenstein's insights on language, meaning, and philosophical problems. The book's fragmentary style and difficult arguments can be frustrating, but many consider it a masterpiece that revolutionized philosophy. Wittgenstein explores how language functions in social contexts, critiques traditional philosophical approaches, and examines concepts like rule-following, private language, and the nature of understanding.

About the Author

Ludwig Josef Johann Wittgenstein was an Austrian-British philosopher who profoundly impacted 20th century philosophy, particularly in logic, philosophy of mathematics, mind, and language. Educated at Cambridge, he was praised by Bertrand Russell as a prime example of genius. Wittgenstein inspired two major philosophical movements: the Vienna Circle and Oxford ordinary language philosophy. His works Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus and Philosophical Investigations are considered among the most important philosophical texts of the 20th century. Wittgenstein's influence extends across humanities and social sciences, though interpretations of his thought vary widely. He is renowned for his passionate, intense approach to philosophical problems.

0:00
-0:00
1x
Dan
Andrew
Michelle
Lauren
Select Speed
1.0×
+
200 words per minute
Home
Library
Get App
Create a free account to unlock:
Requests: Request new book summaries
Bookmarks: Save your favorite books
History: Revisit books later
Recommendations: Get personalized suggestions
Ratings: Rate books & see your ratings
Try Full Access for 7 Days
Listen, bookmark, and more
Compare Features Free Pro
📖 Read Summaries
All summaries are free to read in 40 languages
🎧 Listen to Summaries
Listen to unlimited summaries in 40 languages
❤️ Unlimited Bookmarks
Free users are limited to 10
📜 Unlimited History
Free users are limited to 10
Risk-Free Timeline
Today: Get Instant Access
Listen to full summaries of 73,530 books. That's 12,000+ hours of audio!
Day 4: Trial Reminder
We'll send you a notification that your trial is ending soon.
Day 7: Your subscription begins
You'll be charged on Apr 26,
cancel anytime before.
Consume 2.8x More Books
2.8x more books Listening Reading
Our users love us
100,000+ readers
"...I can 10x the number of books I can read..."
"...exceptionally accurate, engaging, and beautifully presented..."
"...better than any amazon review when I'm making a book-buying decision..."
Save 62%
Yearly
$119.88 $44.99/year
$3.75/mo
Monthly
$9.99/mo
Try Free & Unlock
7 days free, then $44.99/year. Cancel anytime.
Scanner
Find a barcode to scan

Settings
General
Widget
Appearance
Loading...
Black Friday Sale 🎉
$20 off Lifetime Access
$79.99 $59.99
Upgrade Now →